- Commentary
- Open access
- Published:
Variation in the extent to which patient information leaflets describe potential benefits and harms of trial interventions: a commentary
Trials volume 26, Article number: 132 (2025)
Abstract
Clinical trial participants must understand the possible risks and benefits of trial interventions before providing their informed consent to participate. The aim of this commentary is twofold: to summarize the discrepancies in the extent to which patient information leaflets (PILs) list potential benefits and harms of trial interventions; and to highlight subsequent ethical issues that may result from failure to disclose potential benefits or harms . A review of 247 patient information leaflets (PILs) found that the extent to which potential benefits and harms are described varies, with 28 (11%) not describing potential benefits and 23 (9%) not describing potential harms. We argue that there is no principled difference between potential benefits and potential harms (what is helpful for one person could harm another), and the need to disclose potential benefits may be less accepted than the need to disclose all potential harms. Additionally, while it is recognized that failure to mention potential harms may violate the ethical principle of autonomy, it is less well-established that other ethical principles, (the need to avoid harm (non-maleficence) , to help patients (beneficence), and to promote justice) may also be at risk when all potential harms and benefits are not disclosed within PILs. We suggest that the way potential benefits and harms are described within PILs be harmonized according to recently established principles.
Background
Study participants must be informed of the potential risks as well as the potential benefits of trial interventions [1,2,3]. Hence, the Declaration of Helsinki states: “each potential participant must be adequately informed in plain language of … the anticipated benefits and potential risks and burdens... of the research” [3]. This is also what participants want. A recent study asking patient representatives and research ethic committee members (“institutional review boards” in the USA) generated clear consensus that informing trial participants of both potential trial harms as well as potential benefits was desired [4, 5].
Despite the need to mention potential benefits and harms, the extent to which potential benefits are shared with trial participants varies. A review of 33 PILs in the UK found that 3 (9%) did not describe potential harms, and 10 (30%) did not describe potential benefits (see Table 1) [6]. In a larger sample of 214 PILs, 20 (9%) did not disclose potential harms, and 18 (8%) did not disclose potential benefits [7].
On the need to disclose potential benefits and harms
Well-publicized studies such as the Tuskegee Syphilis Study [8] and the Human Radiation Experiments [9] in which people were harmed as a result of not being informed that they were participating in a trial, let alone the risks of the trial, illustrate the dangers of doing research without full disclosure of the risks. While some disagree over correct terminology (“side effect,” “harm,” “safety incident”) [10], withholding knowledge of potential harms, however described, is unlikely to be justifiable given the requirement to disclose information.
Possible exceptions to this rule have been proposed. In one example, it was recommended that potential participants be asked how much they would like to know about potential benefits or harms [11]. If participants consent to remaining uninformed, withholding information might seem acceptable. However, this approach is flawed because participants cannot evaluate what information is being withheld, rendering their choice to remain ignorant essentially uninformed. At best, such a recommendation might apply to the depth of discussion with a clinician about potential harms, but it does not justify omitting critical information about potential harms from the participant information leaflet (PIL).
Others have claimed that it is acceptable to withhold information about potential harms if doing so benefits the participant [12]. For example, informing the participant about some mild harms could lead the participant to expect the harm, and for some types of outcomes (such as pain) the expectation of the harm could even cause the harm (a “nocebo” effect) [13]. However, even if withholding information reduces the risk of some harm, it must be established that the reduced harm outweighs the actual (moral) harm of withholding information. Additionally, there are different ways to explain potential harms, some of which are less likely to cause nocebo effects than others [14]. Hence, it may not be necessary to withhold information about harms to avoid causing nocebo effects. It could also arguably be acceptable to withhold information about potential harms if the intervention is very unlikely to have any adverse effects. For example, one of the PILs within our sample that did not provide any information about possible adverse events was for a trial of reminding school children to brush their teeth [15]. The PIL for this trial did not mention harms, which seems acceptable. However, some of the PILs within our sample that did not mention harms arguably should have. One of these was for a placebo-controlled trial of eculizumab to treat children with a blood disorder called Shiga toxin-producing Escherichia coli hemolytic uremic syndrome (STEC-HUS) [16, 17]. The PIL did not state any of the potential harms following eculizumab treatment, whereas adverse events related to eculizumab for STEC-HUS include neurological impairment and death [18]. (Aside: the trial also used a placebo control whereas there are other available treatments for STEC-HUS such as volume expansion [19]. The use of the placebo control without the inclusion of other potentially helpful interventions is an additional problem [14]).
Failure to mention potential benefits is also problematic. For example, some PILs within our sample stated that there were no potential benefits of the placebo control intervention. This is not the case. While there is a debate about how effective placebo treatments are [20], there is little doubt that they have some effects, including non-specific effects that apply across conditions such as reducing anxiety and pain [14].
A note on the mistaken distinction between potential benefits and potential harms
In December 2020, we participated in a workshop with representatives from the Health Research Authority (HRA), ethics committee members, and trial managers (total 25 participants) [21]. The purpose of the workshop was to co-produce recommendations for developing guidance and resources related to attempts to harmonize the way potential benefits and harms are shared within PILs. Some of the workshop participants expressed a belief that research regulations prohibited discussion of the potential benefits of participating in a study within PILs. The justifications given were that whereas potential harms were allegedly known, potential benefits were not, and that mentioning potential benefits was coercive and possibly illegal. The belief that potential benefits are less certain than potential harms is mistaken. The extent to which potential benefits or harms are known depends on the state of background evidence, which in the case of drugs is related to the phase of the trial (see below). Moreover, there is no fundamental distinction between potential benefits and potential harms, because whether something counts as a benefit or harm is often relative to the individual. For example, a side effect of selective serotonin reuptake inhibitors is sexual dysfunction [22]. This is undesirable to many, but is a benefit to benefit for people with premature ejaculation [22]. Likewise, loss of appetite could be a negative effect of a drug for some but may be judged a positive effect by those who are trying to lose weight. In a more extreme example, morphine slows down bodily functions (considered a harm to many) yet is a benefit to those who are deeply suffering and happy for their functions to slow down painlessly even if it increases the risk of their demise. Hence, mentioning potential risks without mentioning potential benefits is often logically impossible. Regarding whether mentioning potential benefits is coercive, we disagree. While exaggerating potential benefits could be coercive, listing them is not. In fact, withholding information about potential benefits could amount to coercing participants into opting out of trials that could benefit them.
The extent to which potential benefits and harms should be listed depends on the type of trial
Taking drug trials as an exemplar, despite having strong pathophysiologic rationales and data from observational [23] and mechanistic studies, many drugs tested in phase I safety trials fail to translate to the clinical setting [24, 25]. Sometimes, serious unexpected harms are also discovered [26]. Therefore, it is rarely appropriate to emphasize potential benefits at this stage, and it is important to emphasize the possibility of unexpected (potentially serious) harms. However, once drugs demonstrate likely safety in phase I trials and progress to phase II efficacy studies, if some efficacy has been observed in phase I, it becomes increasingly legitimate to mention both potential benefits and harms. Here, claims about potential benefits must remain very tentative because about one in three drugs tested in phase II trials show no efficacy (or are revealed as harmful) and are abandoned [27]. Once the intervention confirms safety and demonstrates some potential benefit in phase II and proceeds to a phase III trial, then it is legitimate to mention both potential benefits and potential harms because both will be evidence-based. Similar principles apply to non-drug trials such as surgical and intervention trials [28], where the certainty with which potential benefits and harms can be claimed increases as the evidence becomes more voluminous and rigorous.
Ethics of failure to mention potential benefits or harms
Autonomy may be compromised by omitting information about potential benefits or harms since withholding this information prevents people making an informed choice [5]. Hence, the World Health Organization’s Declaration of Helsinki [3] as well as requirements for informed consent in the UK [29], USA [30], and the European Union [31], all mention the need to disclose all information about both potential harms and potential benefits. It is less well recognised that other ethical principles may be violated when information about potential benefits or harms is not mentioned. Non-maleficence (the requirement to avoid harm) could be violated if potential benefits are not mentioned since this leads to an unbalanced, over-emphasis on potential harms that increases risk of harmful nocebo effects [6, 32]. Relatedly, people who are scared away from participating in a trial because of failure to mention potential benefits are foregoing an opportunity to gain from the trial, which violates beneficence (the ethical requirement to help whenever possible). Relatedly, again if participants are scared away from a trial because potential benefits are not mentioned alongside potential harms, justice (including fair distribution of resources) could be violated. This is because clinical trials often fail because of difficulties in recruiting and/or retaining patients [33]. Ensuring that potential benefits are described alongside potential risks could also improve recruitment and retention rates [34], thus improving justice by wasting less money on trials that failed to recruit or retain patients.
Solution: describe all potential benefits and potential harms in close proximity
A survey of 250 stakeholders (including patient and public representatives, research ethics committee members, industry representatives, medico-legal experts, psychologists, and trial managers) reached a consensus about seven principles that can be used to harmonize the way potential benefits and harms are shared with participants in trials. These were (1) all potential harms of a given intervention should be listed, (2) all potential harms should be separated into serious and less serious, (3) it must be made explicit that not all potential harms are known, (4) all potential benefits should be listed, (5) all potential benefits and harms need to be compared with what would happen if the participant did not take part in the trial, (6) suitable visual representations should be added where appropriate, and (7) information regarding potential benefits and harms should not be presented apart by one or more pages [5]. Adhering to these principles would ensure inclusion of all known potential benefits and harms within PILs in a way that potential trial participants could straightforwardly compare them, thus potentially improving the ethics of PILs and clinical trials.
Conclusion
Every intervention has potential effects, and these effects will be beneficial to some and harmful to others. Deciding whether to enroll in a trial (or take a medication) relies on weighing up these potential benefits and harms. It is impossible to do this if either the benefits or harms are not mentioned, and it is difficult to do so if the potential benefits and harms are not mentioned in close textual proximity. Trial participants need to be informed of these effects in a way they find acceptable, and there is now an established acceptable method to achieve this which should now be followed.
Data availability
There are no additional data and materials associated with this manuscript.
Abbreviations
- AIDS:
-
Acquired immune deficiency syndrome
- CER:
-
Comparative effectiveness research
- EU:
-
European Union
- HIV:
-
Human immunodeficiency viruses
- IRB:
-
Institutional review boards
- OHRP:
-
Office of Human Research Protections
- PIL:
-
Patient information leaflet
- REB:
-
Research ethics board
References
United States Holocaust Memorial Museum. The doctors trial. 2022. Available from: https://web.archive.org/web/20071011204837/http:/www.ushmm.org/research/doctors/index.html. Accessed 13 Jan 2023.
Centre for Research on Multinational Corporations. SOMO briefing paper on clinical trials #1: examples of unethical trials. Amsterdam: Centre for Research on Multinational Corporations; 2008. Accessed 13 Jan 2023.
World Medical Association. The declaration of helsinki Ferney-Voltaire. WMA; 2013. Available from: https://www.wma.net/policies-post/wma-declaration-of-helsinki-ethical-principles-for-medical-research-involving-human-subjects/. Accessed 7 Jul 2022.
Innes K, Cotton S, Campbell MK, et al. Relative importance of informational items in participant information leaflets for trials: a Q-methodology approach. BMJ Open. 2018;8(9):e023303. https://doiorg.publicaciones.saludcastillayleon.es/10.1136/bmjopen-2018-023303.
Svobodova M, Jacob N, Hood K, et al. Developing principles for sharing information about potential trial intervention benefits and harms with patients: report of a modified Delphi survey. Trials. 2022;23:863. https://doiorg.publicaciones.saludcastillayleon.es/10.1186/s13063-022-06780-1.
Kirby N, Shepherd V, Howick J, et al. Nocebo effects and participant information leaflets: evaluating information provided on adverse effects in UK clinical trials. Trials. 2020;21(1):658. https://doiorg.publicaciones.saludcastillayleon.es/10.1186/s13063-020-04591-w. Published Online First: 2020/07/19.
Cuddihy L, Howick J, Murphy E, et al. When describing harms and benefits to potential trial participants, participant information leaflets are inadequate. Trials. 2024;25(1):292. https://doiorg.publicaciones.saludcastillayleon.es/10.1186/s13063-024-08087-9. Published Online First: 20240501.
Caldwell JG, Price EV, Schroeter AL, et al. Aortic regurgitation in the Tuskegee study of untreated syphilis. J Chronic Dis. 1973;26(3):187–94. Published Online First: 1973/03/01.
Spicer CM. Fallout from government-sponsored radiation research. Kennedy Inst Ethics J. 1994;4(2):147–54. https://doiorg.publicaciones.saludcastillayleon.es/10.1353/ken.0.0137.
Phillips R, Bi D, Goulao B, et al. Public perspective on potential treatment intervention harm in clinical trials-terminology and communication. Trials. 2024;25(1):573. https://doiorg.publicaciones.saludcastillayleon.es/10.1186/s13063-024-08418-w. Published Online First: 20240831.
Oxman AD, Chalmers I, Sackett DL. A practical guide to informed consent to treatment. BMJ. 2001;323(7327):1464–6. Published Online First: 2001/12/26.
Foddy B. A duty to deceive: placebos in clinical practice. Am journal of bioethics : AJOB. 2009;9(12):4–12. https://doiorg.publicaciones.saludcastillayleon.es/10.1080/15265160903318350. Published Online First: 2009/12/17.
Howick J, Webster R, Kirby N, et al. Rapid overview of systematic reviews of nocebo effects reported by patients taking placebos in clinical trials. Trials. 2018;19(1):674. https://doiorg.publicaciones.saludcastillayleon.es/10.1186/s13063-018-3042-4.
Howick J. The power of placebos: how the science of placebos and nocebos can improve health care. Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press; 2023.
Marshman Z, Ainsworth H, Chestnutt IG, Day P, Dey D, El Yousfi S, et al. Brushing RemInder 4 Good oral HealTh (BRIGHT) trial: does an SMS behaviour change programme with a classroom-based session improve the oral health of young people living in deprived areas? A study protocol of a randomised controlled trial. Trials. 2019;20(1). https://doiorg.publicaciones.saludcastillayleon.es/10.1186/s13063-019-3538-6.
Health Research Authority (HRA). ECUSTEC. Health Research Authority (HRA); 2016. Available from: https://www.hra.nhs.uk/planning-and-improving-research/application-summaries/research-summaries/ecustec/. Accessed 7 Mar 2025.
Ives N, Woolley R, Saleem MA, Moakes CA, Waters A, Gilbert RD, et al. Efficacy and safety of eculizumab in children with Shiga-toxin-producing Escherichia coli haemolytic uraemic syndrome: the ECUSTEC RCT. Southampton: National Institute for Health and Care Research; 2024.
Muff-Luett M, Sanderson KR, Engen RM, et al. Eculizumab exposure in children and young adults: indications, practice patterns, and outcomes-a Pediatric Nephrology Research Consortium study. Pediatr Nephrol. 2021;36(8):2349–60. https://doiorg.publicaciones.saludcastillayleon.es/10.1007/s00467-021-04965-5. Published Online First: 20210310.
Liu Y, Thaker H, Wang C, et al. Diagnosis and treatment for Shiga toxin-producing Escherichia coli associated hemolytic uremic syndrome. Toxins (Basel). 2022;15(1). https://doiorg.publicaciones.saludcastillayleon.es/10.3390/toxins15010010. Published Online First: 20221223.
Howick J, Friedemann C, Tsakok M, et al. Are treatments more effective than placebos? A systematic review and meta-analysis. PLoS One. 2013;8(5):e62599. https://doiorg.publicaciones.saludcastillayleon.es/10.1371/journal.pone.0062599.
Jacob N, Howick J, Svobodova M, et al. Co-production of guidance and resources to implement principled participant information leaflets (PrinciPILs). NIHR Open Res. 2023;3(42):42. https://doiorg.publicaciones.saludcastillayleon.es/10.3310/nihropenres.13423.1.
Bala A, Nguyen HMT, Hellstrom WJG. Post-SSRI sexual dysfunction: a literature review. Sex Med Rev. 2018;6(1):29–34. https://doiorg.publicaciones.saludcastillayleon.es/10.1016/j.sxmr.2017.07.002. Published Online First: 2017/08/06.
Howick J, Glasziou P, Aronson JK. Evidence-based mechanistic reasoning. J R Soc Med. 2010;103(11):433–41. https://doiorg.publicaciones.saludcastillayleon.es/10.1258/jrsm.2010.100146.
Howick J. Exposing the vanities – and a qualified defence – of mechanistic evidence in clinical decision-making. Phillosophy of Science. 2011;78(5):926–40.
Hirst JA, Howick J, Aronson JK, et al. The need for randomization in animal trials: an overview of systematic reviews. PLoS One. 2014;9(6):e98856. https://doiorg.publicaciones.saludcastillayleon.es/10.1371/journal.pone.0098856.
Stebbings R, Findlay L, Edwards C, et al. “Cytokine storm” in the phase I trial of monoclonal antibody TGN1412: better understanding the causes to improve preclinical testing of immunotherapeutics. Journal of immunology. 2007;179(5):3325–31. Published Online First: 2007/08/22.
Van Norman GA. Phase II trials in drug development and adaptive trial design. JACC Basic Transl Sci. 2019;4(3):428–37. https://doiorg.publicaciones.saludcastillayleon.es/10.1016/j.jacbts.2019.02.005. Published Online First: 20190624.
National Institutes of Health. NIH clinical research trials and you. 2022. Available from: https://www.nih.gov/health-information/nih-clinical-research-trials-you/basics#:~:text=What%20are%20the%20phases%20of,treatment's%20benefits%2C%20and%20optimal%20use. Accessed 9 Dec 2024.
Legislation.gov.uk. The medicines for human use (clinical trials) regulations 2004. London: The National Archives; 2004. Available from: https://www.legislation.gov.uk/uksi/2004/1031/schedule/1/made. Accessed 6 Jan 2023.
Office for Human Research Protections. 2018 requirements (2018 Common rule). Rockville: Department of Health and Human Services (HHS); 2018. Available from: https://www.hhs.gov/ohrp/regulations-and-policy/regulations/45-cfr-46/revised-common-rule-regulatory-text/index.html. Accessed 6 Jan 2023.
EUR-Lex. Regulation (EU) No 536/2014 of the European Parliament and of the Council of 16 April 2014 on clinical trials on medicinal products for human use, and repealing directive 2001/20/EC Text with EEA relevance 2022. Available from: https://eur-lex.europa.eu/eli/reg/2014/536/oj. Accessed 6 Jan 2023.
Howick J. Saying things the “right” way: avoiding “nocebo” effects and providing full informed consent. Am J Bioeth. 2012;12(3):33–4. https://doiorg.publicaciones.saludcastillayleon.es/10.1080/15265161.2012.656799.
Treweek S, Pitkethly M, Cook J, et al. Strategies to improve recruitment to randomised trials. Cochrane Database Syst Rev. 2018;2:MR000013. https://doiorg.publicaciones.saludcastillayleon.es/10.1002/14651858.MR000013.pub6.
Centre for Trials Research. PrinciPILs. Wales: Cardiff University; 2021. Available from: https://www.cardiff.ac.uk/centre-for-trials-research/research/studies-and-trials/view/principil. Accessed 19 Aug 2022.
Acknowledgements
None.
Funding
JH, MS, NJ, ST, PB, AE, KG, JB, and KH were funded by the Medical Research Council (MRA reference MR/V020706/1). JH is also funded by the Stoneygate Trust. The funders nor the sponsor was involved in any other aspect of the project, such as the design of the project’s protocol and analysis plan, the collection, and analyses.
Author information
Authors and Affiliations
Contributions
Conceptualization: JH, JL; methodology: JH, JL, MS, NJ, ST, PB, AE, KG, JB, KH; funding acquisition: JH, ST, PB, AE, KG, JB, KH; project administration: JH, MS; supervision: JH; writing—original draft: JH, JL; writing—review and editing: JH, JL, MS, NJ, ST, PB, AE, KG, JB, KH.
Corresponding author
Ethics declarations
Ethics approval and consent to participate
Not relevant: this manuscript did not involve any study subjects.
Consent for publication
Not relevant: this manuscript did not involve any study subjects.
Competing interests
ST is an Editor-in-Chief of Trials.
Additional information
Publisher’s Note
Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.
Rights and permissions
Open Access This article is licensed under a Creative Commons Attribution 4.0 International License, which permits use, sharing, adaptation, distribution and reproduction in any medium or format, as long as you give appropriate credit to the original author(s) and the source, provide a link to the Creative Commons licence, and indicate if changes were made. The images or other third party material in this article are included in the article's Creative Commons licence, unless indicated otherwise in a credit line to the material. If material is not included in the article's Creative Commons licence and your intended use is not permitted by statutory regulation or exceeds the permitted use, you will need to obtain permission directly from the copyright holder. To view a copy of this licence, visit http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/.
About this article
Cite this article
Howick, J., Lantos, J.D., Treweek, S. et al. Variation in the extent to which patient information leaflets describe potential benefits and harms of trial interventions: a commentary. Trials 26, 132 (2025). https://doiorg.publicaciones.saludcastillayleon.es/10.1186/s13063-025-08824-8
Received:
Accepted:
Published:
DOI: https://doiorg.publicaciones.saludcastillayleon.es/10.1186/s13063-025-08824-8